Recently, Prof. Liam Delaney induced an online discussion about “historical works (say pre-1950) that are most worthwhile to read for people interested in contemporary behavioural science and behavioural economics debates”. This reminded me of a time, a bit more than 10 years ago, when I was graduating in Economics and got interested in studying topics on human decision under uncertain and choice over time. I started with contemporaneous readings, for instance David Laibson’s work on time inconsistent decisions, Daniel Kahneman’s Nobel Prize Lecture, Matthew Rabin’s essay on Psychology and Economics and Colin Camerer and George Loewenstein’s draft about the advancements in Behavioural Economics. After having read those insightful pieces, a question came to my mind: when was elaborated the first intellectual description of human decision making under uncertainty? From undergraduate textbooks, I knew that a canonical normative model had been developed in the 1940s by John von Neumann and Oscar Morgenstern’s proposition of expected utility theory, and that modern financial theory had foundations on the Arrow-Pratt measure of risk aversion. But because the concept of utility appeared much earlier in Economic thought, I also wondered about the existence of previous approaches to price bets, insurance premiums, and lotteries.
Hopefully, I ended up knowing about two historical works that introduced the fundamental principles of human decisions under uncertainty and which I think are most worthwhile for people interested in behavioural science to at least be aware of their existence: (i) the Principle of Expected Value; and (ii) the Principle of Expected Utility.
Hopefully, I ended up knowing about two historical works that introduced the fundamental principles of human decisions under uncertainty and which I think are most worthwhile for people interested in behavioural science to at least be aware of their existence: (i) the Principle of Expected Value; and (ii) the Principle of Expected Utility.
Blaise Pascal (1623-1662) |
Pascal’s idea of pricing a bet according to its mathematical expectation is quite simple: the expected value of a bet is equivalent to its weighted average, or the sum of its possible n payoffs xi multiplied by their correspondent probabilities pi of occurrence. Then, the value of a bet L is:
Few decades later, doubts were raised about the adequacy of a simple mathematical expectation as a way to describe human decisions under risk. For example, how could it explain the attitude of traders paying insurance premiums to cover their ships that were apparently higher than the price implied by the expected losses in case of accident or piracy? Thus, the behaviour of a prudent trader would be a clear violation of the expected value’s hypothesis.
Daniel Bernoulli (1700-1782) |
Daniel Bernoulli’s insight to solve this puzzling fact was to observe that the expected value of a bet is equivalent to its ‘real world’ value if, and only if, we implicitly assume that the subjective value of money – utility – is equal to its objective value. He expressed his idea by making use of a logarithm function, stating that the utility derived from money or wealth is described by a concave function, so as wealth increases, the marginal utility of money decreases. He showed these ideas in his solution to the St. Petersburg Paradox, proposed by his cousin Nicholas Bernoulli.
Consider, for example, a situation of two players, Peter and Paul, who play the following coin flipping bet:
- If the outcome in the first round is head, Peter wins and Paul pays him $2 and the bet ends;
- If Peter loses the first round but wins the second, Paul pays him $4 and the bet ends;
- If Peter loses n-1 rounds but wins the nth round, Paul pays him $2n and the bet ends.
The problem here consists on determining the amount that Peter should pay Paul in exchange for the offer made. According to the expected value method, Peter should pay an infinite amount of money:
Now, applying the principle of expected utility, for example with a natural logarithm function, the outcome is much more plausible:
If the subjective value of the bet is 1.3863, then its predicted objective value V in the real world is:
If the subjective value of the bet is 1.3863, then its predicted objective value V in the real world is:
So according to the expected utility principle, Peter would pay a maximum of $4.00 in order to play the game.
In a follow up post, I will elaborate on Bernoulli’s proposition, specifically on its link with Prospect Theory and what Professor Kahneman calls Bernoulli’s error. #BEHistorical
No comments:
Post a Comment